C.S. Lewis: His Theology and Philosophy - Lesson 8
Mere Christianity (Part 5)
Theism is intellectually at least on par, if not superior to, other conceptions of reality like dualism, pantheism and naturalism. If there is a God that theism describes, only one deity of the living theistic religions said that this God invaded our existence. The question is that in comparison to other alternatives, what is emerging as a reasonable explanation of the reality we face?
Mere Christianity (Part 5)
I. Different Conceptions of God
A. Theism
B. Atheism
C. The question of suffering and evil that reality contains
D. Sinful human nature
II. The Shocking Alternative
A. How God makes himself known to humans
1. Conscience (moral awareness)
2. Good dreams
B. Objections to Jesus
C. Liar, lunatic and Lord trilemna
D. The practical conclusion is that we should seek this new life
Dr. Michael Peterson
C.S. Lewis: His Theology and Philosophy
ap530-08
Mere Christianity (Part 5)
Lesson Transcript
Back to Lewis in mere Christianity. We're just kind of serving his line of thought. He thinks he's got theism on the table. He's going to make mention here at the beginning of his second book, The Rival Conceptions of God is how he labels this book. He's going to say some things that we've already discussed to some extent about how theism is intellectually every bit as much on par, if not intellectually superior to these other conceptions pantheism, dualism, so on. So I'll move on. But he says now, if there is a God out there, the theism describes the only only one theism among the great living theistic religions says that this God invaded our existence. And that's Christianity. So it does part company in that regard on being incarnation all. And then it's a very short move to have a part company being Trinitarian. And that's where he's headed. Ultimately, the book ends with an amazing presentation of Trinitarian understanding. But he wants to get to the Incarnation. So we've done we've done theism to some extent. There's a series of series of radio broadcasts. He thinks it's intellectually credible. He's made some comments about alternative positions that are less credible. So if there's much credible, he's raising the question, wouldn't it be something if that God made himself known in a concrete way in human history? And he says, as hard as it might seem at first to believe, that's exactly what Christianity is claiming. And he says, now, in addition to these rival conceptions of God or rival conceptions of the ultimate, there, of course, is atheism, which rejects all religious conceptions. And he says the trouble with atheism is it's too simple. And reality is not simple. Reality is complex. It's textured. It takes careful and deep analysis.
And he thinks that atheism does not give reality as deep and analysis as it deserves. And he believes that a case can be made. That part of the complexity of the reality we inhabit is that it's been invaded by a unique personality. And that, of course, is going to be a person who claims to be God. Now. Where we're atheism he thinks makes a lot of its living is on the suffering and evil that reality contains. And so he does talk a little bit about that and he brings back up dualism. So he dualism has an explanation of why there's evil. The good power has some force, it has some attractiveness. Just like I say, the good part of the evil power, the evil power has some force, and that's why there's evil. The good powers resisting. They're fighting, they're struggling. So he's basically saying that dualism has it's its view. We've discussed that to some extent, but atheism wants to go ahead and say, well, there must be no divine being, no ultimate good, because there's too much suffering. But of course, his point with the atheist and with the net that which in our day and time atheism is really not an explanation of much, but it's not a worldview. It's just the denial that there's a God or there's any God or any religion is valid. Atheism needs its own worldview. Home and the natural worldview. Home of atheism in secularized Western society is is naturalism. Naturalism gives you the explanation how nothing but physical stuff is real. There are no absolute values. Morality is relative, generally speaking, for most naturalists and so on and so on. And so atheism is an implication of naturalism as a larger worldview. So he's basically saying that How can you have such a serious objection, which is rational and moral in the way it's presented that a good God, if he exists, would not allow evil and suffering, or he wouldn't allow as much as there is in the world.
When you don't believe that there's a standard of good and evil by which you can make that statement. And so this is a sort of saying about dualism. How do you prefer one power over the other? It's a similar move he makes logically with a naturalist slash atheist saying, how can you raise a rational moral objection when you don't have an ultimate standard of morality anchored in the ultimate reality of the universe, which is physical stuff matter? Again, these are not systematic refutations. They're highly suggestive of where you could take an academic exchange, a real technical argument and counter argument with atheism over the problem of evil. Lewis does not wage that complete argument. He can't wage any complete argument. He's moving along in his talks, his radio broadcasts. But just so we put him in interaction with the issues and with the major voices and the major options. I want to make sure we see how is not hard to elevate what Louis was saying, sophisticated a little bit, given the way he expresses it. And he's certainly on a trajectory, in my opinion, that's going in a good place philosophically and theologically, takes no back seat to any other major world view option. So he gets to the point where he's saying that. Sin and evil in the world has created distance between us and God, humans and God. It's created damage. One of his favorite words is damage. We're damaged and the cure is healing and wholeness. They'll come up later, too, but we're damaged. And we can't help ourselves. He does want to make sure. That we don't think as a as some forms of dualism do, the human nature is innately evil. And we had that discussion before the break.
But Lewis's Lewis's I think he's right on here. It's an Augustinian view that something created by God can never be intrinsically evil. I do think we need to, since he's an Anglican slash Catholic small C in his orientation, we need to make a distinction in how this word sinful human nature is used, because nature often refers to what it is that makes you the kind of thing that you are, what it is that makes you the kind of thing that you are. Without it, you wouldn't be the kind of thing that you are without the need. The nature of being a zebra, the nature of this, nature of that. But I think there's there's room for a very careful, very important distinction between the philosophical and theological use of the term sinful human nature. The word nature philosophically is a metaphysical concept. It has to do with what makes anything the kind of thing that it is. Without it, you're just not that kind of thing. So human nature, philosophically, with its metaphysical meaning, means rational, moral, personal, bodily, finite. You know, being and that's the kind of thing we are. And God calls it good in the Genesis story, very good horror, biblical language, and it's picked up in much theological pronouncements, is that human nature is is sinful and you've got more of a moral, spiritual, um, I would say kind of relational point that theology is making, which is different. But I think people mistakenly think, oh, theology trumps philosophy. Big mistake. A very competitive no. But so that if theology is now saying that human nature is sinful by nature, by nature, we're sinful, that we can no longer say by nature we are good over here. This is good. Metaphysically, creation of God cannot change.
It cannot change. So the fall into sin is doing something else than changing our metaphysical nature. It's changing a relationship. It's damaging us. Just as Lewis says. Another place, it's warping us. This stays the same. Over on the left. I think you have to defend that. And this has become a real problem. This is the same problem. So if God can deal with the same problem and remove sin. The ultimately victorious over sin in our lives. We remain this kind of thing metaphysically. That's the kind of thing we are to turn into a zebra or become something non-human. Without the properties of being human, rational, moral, spiritual will. All those properties, they stay the same. But now they're fully operative. They're healed, restored, redeemed, uplifted, transformed. That's the goal, is what has been damaged. Marred. Bent, as he says in one place. It's got a whole chapter called Bent Man later in the book. So I think that's very important. And Louis falls on this side of the distinction, knowing that this is a relational matter and that nothing changed in our metaphysical nature. I sense that Louis feels like with the Reformation, there's less clarity about that. To follow that point up. I gave you a supplemental reading by the French Jesuit Claude Treisman tonight on the Metaphysics of Human Nature, and that's in the online classroom. And he works through this from a philosophical point of view. He's right on with Lewis. Now. The point then for Lewis in surveying the options, everything from dualism on one side of the spectrum to atheism and its natural home in materialism and naturalism. On the other side, he calls the shocking alternative to their inadequacies, which he thinks is pointed out in a kind of a lay, competent lay way.
He's not trying to be a technician and and do this in a real sophisticated academic way. But he's pointing out the inadequacies of the shocking alternative Christianity is claiming is that the divine behind the universe has made himself known within the universe, and even rationally, without knowing how he's made himself known within the universe and in a concrete person, we've already rationally come to believe it's credible that he exists because the moral argument he's run and the way he's shown inadequacies of alternative views. So it's thought he has already got it on the table. He wants to make that further move now that God has become incarnate. Again for a lay audience on the BBC. So he says, How does God come to make himself known? Well, he's given us conscience. That starts the book. The moral awareness we have that gives his argument for the existence of a moral being some traction. And he goes as far as he can with that. He says, God gives us good dreams. I take by that the rich and full sense of we have some idea of what life could be like if sin were not in the position it is. And later, there's going to be what has come to be known in Lewis's writings as the argument from desire. So it could be he's alluding a little bit here with good dreams, the good dreams language to the idea that we have. We have dreams. We we desire something beyond the world as we know it that the world itself cannot fulfill, cannot provide us with. But we seem made for that. We long for that. Can we call this the Louisa in argument from desire? So God gives us conscience, moral awareness. God gives us, quote unquote, good dreams, he says.
But he says God also gives us particular people. Particular people. And he says, Of course, there's one person in particular who came in first century Nazareth and claimed to have the power to forgive sins, the things that are relationally wrong on the far side of the chart over there. He he claims to be able to deal with on our behalf. And that is a shocking claim. So the shocking alternative, he says the invasion, he says, is that Christianity looks as reasonable, if not more reasonable, than the alternatives when we think about it and we follow its logic. So because we've damaged ourselves in relations, properly speaking between us and God have been broken, we are powerless to fix the problem. So he's not quoting the Bible. He's talking to a broadly secular audience in the forties in England, and he's saying, Here's a person who claims to be the solution to the problem. Now, again, without quoting the Bible and keeping on his main theme of making this reasonably believable and not just reasonably believable in its own right. But part of his strategy is, by comparison, all the way to other alternatives dualism, pantheism. And so it's always, comparatively speaking, this makes better sense. So he knows that there are objections to the claim that Christ is definitive. The Christ is sent from God to deal with the same problem. And that has become an interesting discussion in Lewis that some scholars in philosophy and some theologians have written about. It's called The Liar, Lunatic and Lord Trilemma. So he knows are some objections. To this claim. For the singularity. Of Jesus. For His uniqueness. For his power to deal with sins. So we often talk about dilemmas to alternatives. We've got to work out which one we should choose, because we can't choose both.
But, you know, you've got to think, well, what is a lemma? It's a line of reasoning. And so there can be two lines of reasoning and you follow their conclusions. You know, you can't you can't accept both. They're incompatible. But likewise, there could be more than to die, to be more than two lines. There could be three. You could have a quadruple lemma. But I'm not into that these days. It's mid-afternoon was kind of a caloric deficit, I think, at work here. And so I can't get into a quadruple lemma. But what we have in Lewis is what's often called a tri lemma three lines of reasoning. And if we're going to set this up in informal logic, not that you've been begging for formal it's logic, but maybe this will be a pick me up or something for the mid-afternoon slump. We often use the wedge as a symbol for and so we can say y. Oops, liar. Tick or Lord. So you're presented with three alternatives. And the way we often do a dilemma, lets say P or Q is I try to find out which one is false or unacceptable. Deny it. You draw the opposite or you draw the other one. So this would be an argument structure. It's called Disjunctive Syllogism in Elementary Logic. But given two alternatives. P or Q if I know the P is false, I should conclude. I have to conclude Q If I know this is true and if I know this is true, this must be true by very simple deductive logic. So if it's true that either P or Q is true. And I know the P is not. Then Q must be. Okay. Disjunctive syllogism in logic. You can Google this. Same thing here.
Now you've got P or Q or R three alternatives. So what you need is you need two more premises, not just one. And the premises would be something like not P, not Q. Therefore, are I going to knock this one out, Go knock this one out in order to be left with this one over here with a dilemma. I just had to knock this one out, which I did right here to get to be left with this one. So Lewis sets it up this way. You can imagine for a radio audience this B, I think this would be so effective. And some of the criticism and discussion will be, is it just rhetorically effective? But it doesn't carry much logical punch. C So that could be some of the of the discussion. So he says there are objections to the claim that Jesus is Lord. One kind of objection would be that he's a person who was a fraud. He's a person who's a liar. Another objection was he wasn't trying to defraud people with his claims. He wasn't just intentionally lying, but somehow he'd come to a mentality. Mental state, maybe a little dysfunctional lunatic is often the word, you know. But somehow he was not quite mentally balanced. And he made these claims with no real devious, you know, intention. But he's still he's a lunatic, but he's definitely not law. So if you can get any of these others to to be reasonable, this would be the least favorite option for those who want to object. Right. Now, when he sets up the trilemma, by the way, he says some people think it's a quadruple lemma. I said I wasn't going to do this because I'm sensing that mid-afternoon ensnares SAG, you know.
But he said he said, I'm not I'm going to do a quadruple lemma put over here. So good. More teacher, if you will make it a quadruple. He says, I'm not going to allow that. He says it comes down to a trilemma. He says, No good moral teacher who's still just a human. Not God would make these kinds of claims. You can't. He says that option is not open to any of his objectors. Actually, I think that's a pretty good point. So it's not a quadruple lemma. But Lewis does flirt with the idea that some people think that's a good option. He says, no, no, you're going to have to you're going to have to deal with the real options. And there are three. His point then, if he wants the third option to seem reasonable is he's going to have to go through and take out these others, make them less credible, make them seem unacceptable. So they're getting too technical. He goes through and just makes a brief case that it's not very credible, that Jesus was just outright lying about himself and that the unaccountably many people who have benefited from his teachings, who have believed his Lord had transformed lives. That hardly makes the liar option look like it's a an option that comes out of deep analysis. Likewise, the lunatic option he was so coherent, seemed to live such a loving, balanced life, was admired and loved by so many. But it doesn't make sense to say he was insane. He was deluded. You know, he thinks these are less likely options. So there's no proof. And I don't think I don't think anybody's offering this as a proof. Proof is only the sort of thing you can find in mathematics and geometry and basic logic sciences even do proofs.
They talk about evidence and making sense of evidence in light of various alternative hypotheses and which hypothesis makes sense. But they still they still put the hypotheses as alternatives. You can't have it all. So even in science hypothesis one or hypothesis two or hypothesis three, and yet you're really dealing with them not as a proof, even though this is a deductive structure which proofs have you're dealing with, what's the probability or the percentage, so to speak, rational believability, the credibility of this hypothesis, this hypothesis, this one and he thinks relative to one another, since since you absolutely cannot have the hypothesis that he was merely a good human teacher. That's not available to the to the objector. He thinks that these hypotheses have less probability, less credibility than saying stunning as it may seem. It looks like it's it's credible among the alternate because there aren't any other alternatives. What could have hypothetically been a quadro Lima got cut down to a tri lima. And then the other two options in the trilemma made to look not very strong. So this emerges. Yes. So as I was reading this to you, I was first reading and thinking that, okay, is avoiding the bursting of the world religions to God's word. And then he goes to God. But I was thinking, though, if you would consider the moral teacher, then you would have to reengage all these. Good point. Because a lot of them see Jesus as that. So if that's true and let them have their own good moral teachers. I love Confucius. I think he's fantastic. But I'm not big on Gautama. He left his wife and children to seek enlightenment, became the Buddha, which means the enlightened one. Never see his wife and kid again.
So that's not very cool in my book. And so but, I mean, you know, that is I'm not trying to offer an ad hominem and ad hominem argument, which means if I can attack the fallibility in the person, what he says is false. Because, I mean, you could attack all of my own foul abilities, right, to try to take out the claim. Kentucky will win the NCAA basketball title in April, but the claim would remain true even though you took me out as a a fallible person. So you can't really say, well, he's a failed person. His claims are false. They'll be dealt with on their own terms. Basketball analogy never hurts. But at any rate, that's a good point. And they have their own moral teachers such as Confucius, such as Little SU, such as others and Zoroaster for the Zoroastrians go on and on. And so if he's merely a good mortage, he's one among many. And you can find resonances even with their teachings across religions. There are some resonance, certainly are usually affirmation for persons of the value being a person of value, of having good relationships with other persons, some resonances even in moral obligations, moral duties. But that's a good point. That's a good point. He really thinks he's effectively blocked that out. What I did was give you some supplementary material. And one piece by Dan Howard Snyder, who used to be at Seattle Pacific for the longest time, and now he's at Western Washington University teaching on the same faculties his wife Frances, actually. And he's pretty critical of this as a logical piece. He's willing to admit it's rhetorical force, it's rhetorical impact, but he's critical of it as a as. Sort of a a really good piece of apologetics, you might say.
Then I put a piece by Steve Davis, who still is at. Seattle Pacific argued against Howard Snyder's critique of Lewis. So here's this little, you know, paragraph in Lewis, which really these are good philosophers. Daniel Snyder is particularly good philosopher, I think. Steve Davis Doggone good philosopher too. And they see it differently. What what Davis recognizes up front is that we multiply probabilities. And and that's not a good way to he says to look at this. I know I shouldn't have done this. A and B and C, I'll just leave it there. Ultimately, if this is point five probability and this is the lowest point for let's say this .64, whatever, you assign some kind of probability function, when you get the probability of the whole set, you have to multiply and you actually diminish probabilities. And we do know that, for example, what's the probability of my flipping this coin? If my wife would just give me any money, she didn't give me minus one. So I've got the imaginary coin my wife should have given me. Flip it. Probability of heads or tails? 5050. Was it heads? Probably 50% was probability of flipping heads twice in a row. 25%. So on one flip my a flip. Point five How about my B flip coin? Five So the chances of two flips in a row being heads is multiplicative. .25. And he's addressing a kind of a an approach out there to Christianity and to object to Christianity saying, wow, if we take all the claims of Christianity, the chances in any one of them are true, are small, and the class chances that they're all true together are just outlandishly small. In a nutshell, the response is, and I would make this in a nutshell, because we've got to move on.
Any complex scientific theory, for example, is going to have statements that have individual probability values. But among the alternatives, there is always assumptions about this theory. It's about how does it fare among alternatives. And so they are also going to have their own internal breakdown of probabilities that gets multiplied as well. Something's going to be true of reality, which is complex, and that's why the theory is complex. So just as you said earlier, reality is complex. Our understanding and analysis of it has become plex. Don't be surprised if you get a relatively complex answer in the form of Christian doctrine and Christian understanding to the key to the reality we we inhabit. But it is true in a technical way that the likelihood of any of those statements being true individually is what it is. And if you put it in a probability classroom in a clinical setting, you'd multiply it out and say in advance, in advance, not looking at any other alternatives either with Hinduism, Buddhism, whatever, or in advance not looking at any of the conceptual core like dualism or pantheon in advance. If you're looking just at Christianity, the probability is true. A small. For all of its claims. It's a technical point. And and the key, I think, is to see that the strategy is not to take Christianity by itself and try to argue that it's highly probable. The key is to contextualize it in a discussion with other alternatives, all of which have their own internal probabilities a priori in advance. The probability of any of them are true in advance when they're isolated is small. So that's never been the question. The question is, in comparison to other alternatives, what is emerging as a reasonable explanation of the reality we face? And even when it comes to the phenomenon of of the life and teachings of Jesus.
What's a reasonable explanation of that? And so he says this level, he thinks the conclusion that he's Lord makes better sense than the other alternatives. But you could put that same kind of reasoning to work with respect to Christians. What's the likelihood God's a trinity? What's the likelihood that he'll be incarnate? What's the likely. Well, they're all the same thing. They're all 5050, which seems high to me. But ultimate reality is is perfectly loving, perfectly good Trinitarian in nature, although it seems very, very small. There's just never was the question. Question is how is it fair in its explanatory value, given the relevant facts and phenomena compared to alternatives? That's a totally different question. I could take I mean, take the take the sickly little tree out back in my yard. What are the chances it'll get struck by lightning? Very small, but lightning strikes somewhere all time. So once a strikes, probability is very high. What is it? We get about 3000 lightning strikes a day on earth somewhere. It's a it's a big number things. Maybe that's a small number, maybe bigger than 3000. But it's it's an interesting number. Well, then the practical conclusion he thinks, is when we're looking at alternatives, which is about Jesus as a very specific subject or Christianity in comparison to other alternatives, as a larger kind of worldview comparison exercise. He thinks that's the way that and I guess you'd say an apologetic approach should go is never saying, Here's the data. Bing, bing, bing. Therefore, man, you'd better. You had better give in to my conclusion because of this data. He's never resting it on quite that kind of an argument pattern, but rather an argument pattern that is in dialog with and comparison with other alternatives, which makes better sense.
That changes the question. Questions. Comments. You know, if we had a lot more time, we could we could put the Davis and Howard Snyder articles out for extensive discussion. But I think we can't. We've got to we've got to keep moving. But he does say that then the practical conclusion from all this reasoning, he thinks he's moving quickly in a way with his radio talks. Given where we've risen to so far, the practical conclusion is we should seek this new life that Christ offers. We should see Him as Lord, and if we see Him as Lord, practically speaking, we have to come to Him as Lord. So we should receive the kind of life that Christ offers. He's saying this on the BBC. He says, This is more than trying to follow the teachings. It's also engaging in the mysterious, mystical union with God and the transformation that it brings. Talks about different means of grace in in life. And I won't go into all those. He just mentions sacraments and so on. But that takes us to the end of book two, the kind of the bridge between theism and Christianity. And he calls book three Christian behavior. So what Christians believe they believe Christ was God, yet put that at the centerpiece when you're presenting it, He thinks, because that's the central claim. If it weren't for that idea that God has become one with a with a historical human being. Christianity wouldn't be what it is. They would be much more on par with the other world religions, all the differences and all the different ways of seeking God. But here's the way God seeks us and seeks intimate union with us. So that's Christian belief. So we are from Theism First chapter.
Our first book gets us to the point of theism and then Christian belief. And now Christian behavior is what's coming up. But I think we need a break on this one. And we'll see in about eight or 10 minutes. Okay.
- 0% CompleteThe purpose of the class is to directly engage Lewis’s philosophy and theology. He brings a Christian worldview to engage intellectual movements of his day. The trinity created us to bring us into the fellowship that has been going on with God forever.0% Complete
- Discover how C.S. Lewis's journey from atheism to Christian apologist highlights the importance of integrating reason and imagination in faith, providing a comprehensive framework for understanding life and spiritual truths through accessible narratives.0% Complete
- This lesson teaches you to value creation, understand the Incarnation, see all life as sacramental, appreciate human personhood, recognize the relationship between evolution and divine creation, and grasp the interconnectedness of truth, the recognition of evil, sensitivity to suffering, commitment to community, and the concept of vocation.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore how Lewis's defense of realism supports the moral argument for a higher power. Learn how he addresses objections from reductionism and evolutionary biology, using a comparative approach to argue that theism offers a more compelling explanation for morality.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore Lewis's moral argument for a theistic god, learning how he handles objections, realism in moral law, epistemic defeaters, and the comparison of worldviews, ultimately positioning theism as a rational choice and setting the stage for discussing Christianity.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore the comparative probability of morality under different worldviews, ultimately arguing that theism provides a more coherent and objective basis for moral awareness than alternatives like Hinduism, dualism, or naturalism, and prepare to integrate Christian concepts into this framework.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore theistic beliefs through moral experience, examine rival conceptions of God, compare dualism and pantheism, and discuss the Christian perspective on good, evil, and salvation, emphasizing the importance of credible and respectful presentations of faith to nonbelievers.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteGain understanding of C.S. Lewis's argument for the intellectual credibility of theism and Christianity, his critique of atheism and other worldviews, the trilemma of Jesus, and the relational nature of sin and redemption.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteGain insight into epistemic realism, the reliability of rational powers, common sense realism, critiques of philosophical skepticism, the development of moral virtues, and a critical examination of Christian sexual morality and marriage dynamics.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteLearn about Mark Noll's critique of evangelical anti-intellectualism, emphasizing the need for intellectual engagement in faith, using C.S. Lewis's balanced approach to faith and reason as a model.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteLearn that Lewis's argument from desire posits that our inherent desire for ultimate fulfillment suggests the existence of a transcendent reality beyond this world, identified as God.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteUnderstand the theological view that God, as an eternal and personal being, models personhood, with practical theology guiding beliefs, the distinction between finite creation and eternal begetting, the relational and dynamic nature of the Trinity, and the transformative journey towards divine life.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore the transition from C.S. Lewis's "Christianity" to "Miracles," emphasizing the clash between naturalism and supernaturalism, the BioLogos conference's role in reconciling faith and science, and Lewis's arguments from the inside to address Hume's epistemological challenge regarding miracles.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteLearn about C.S. Lewis's comparison of naturalism and supernaturalism, his criteria for evaluating worldviews, and the challenges naturalism faces regarding rationality and mind theories, highlighting theism's explanatory superiority.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteWhat’s important to Lewis is freedom of rational thinking, free from physical causes. Naturalism undercuts the power of reason because everything is determined by physical causes. If evolutionary naturalism is true, then the probability of our cognitive faculties being reliable for truth is low.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore the interplay between reason, naturalism, and evolution through the perspectives of C.S. Lewis and Alvin Plantinga, focusing on the need for free will in rational thought, the reliability of cognitive faculties, and the limitations of naturalism and evolution in ensuring truth-aimed beliefs.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteThis lesson examines the mind-brain relationship through emergent dualism, explaining how complex brain functions lead to higher mental processes and exploring the interplay between rational thought, moral consciousness, and the perspectives of science and religion on miracles.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteThis lesson explains that divine actions are not violations of natural laws but purposeful interventions where God alters usual conditions, challenging Hume's regularity theory and emphasizing the need for an interpretive framework for understanding miracles.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteLearn to create a coherent narrative, address emotional objections to theism, contrast non-theist and theist views of nature, understand the Christian creation doctrine, emphasize monotheism, critique pantheism, and explore Greek and Hebrew theological elements.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteC.S. Lewis argues that miracles are possible if God is a determinant being outside the natural system. He distinguishes between good and bad miracles and stresses understanding the grand narrative to judiciously judge their credibility.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteIn philosophy, it’s referred to as the problem of evil. Given a certain understanding of God and a certain understanding of evil, there is a tension explaining why evil exists in the world.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore Lewis's view on divine omnipotence, the independent operation of physical laws, the role of pain in achieving higher divine purposes, and the distinction between true goodness and mere kindness, with implications for pastoral care and counseling.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore Camus' existential journey and private spiritual search through his conversations with Reverend Moomaw, revealing his dissatisfaction with atheistic existentialism and his secret visits to church, ultimately acknowledging a need for God.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteGod is his creation set forth the problem of expressing his goodness through the total drama of a world containing free agents in spite of, and even by means of, their rebellion against him. The risk is for the possibility of relationship.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteAristotle would say that as a rational, moral being you build your character based on the hierarchy of good traits. From a Christian perspective, our natural destiny should be on the same trajectory as our eternal destiny. The spiritual and theological virtues are faith, hope and love.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore pain's inherent role in the biological system, the theological and scientific perspectives on its origins, human freedom's impact, the concept of gratuitous evil, and how pain highlights human vulnerability and dependence on God.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteLewis thinks that God needs to pierce the shield of our ego and we are embodied creatures so pain is what does it by getting our attention by highlighting how frail and in need we are.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore Lewis's view on animal pain as distinct from human pain, linked to Cartesian dualism, evolutionary necessity, theological implications, and the potential redemption of the animal kingdom.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteThe lesson focuses on the themes of dichotomy, the intertwining of love and pain, and the acknowledgment of suffering as a component of true happiness, both in the present and future contexts.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteExplore how pain and happiness coexist through C.S. Lewis's reflections in "A Grief Observed," his journey through grief, and philosophical considerations of materialism versus faith, emphasizing the relational nature of the universe and the hope of resurrection.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteLearn that "The Great Divorce" shows heaven and hell as mutually exclusive, explore God's reality as the ultimate truth, and understand the journey from self-absorption to eternal joy through a symbolic dream narrative and character analyses.0% Complete
- 0% CompleteFinal comments about themes in The Great Divorce.0% Complete
Resources
About BiblicalTraining.org
BiblicalTraining.org wants every Christian to experience a deep and loving relationship with Jesus by understanding the life-changing truths of Scripture. To that end, we provide a high-quality Bible education at three academic levels taught by a wide range of distinguished professors, pastors, authors, and ministry leaders that moves from content to spiritual growth, all at no charge. We are a 501(c)(3) non-profit funded by gifts from our users. We currently have over 180 classes and seminars, 2,300 hours of instruction, registered users from every country in the world, and in the last two years 1.4 million people watched 257 terabytes of videos (11 million lectures).
Our goal is to provide a comprehensive biblical education governed by our Statement of Faith that leads people toward spiritual growth.